goriano Wrote:Could you explain why (B) is wrong? I thought it mirrored the flaw by going from THAT ticket/THAT horse to ALL tickets/ALL horses?
You're right that (B) does go from a specific premise to a general conclusion.
However, the flaw in the original is taking one trait [reasonable to believe that it will lose] and saying, since that trait applies to each individual ticket, we may conclude that that trait applies to all tickets.
In (B), the trait that applies to the specific premise is [reasonable to believe that it will win], while the trait applied in the conclusion is [reasonable to believe it will
not win].
Here's another distinction:
In the original argument, the specific thing discussed in the premise is a subset of the larger group discussed in the conclusion.
In (B), the specific horse discussed in the premise is NOT a subset of the larger group discussed in the conclusion (the conclusion is about the group of all horses other than that premise-horse).
FYI, on Matching questions, beware the "Topic Trap" - answer choices that seem to be very close in topic to the original argument. (The test wants matching logic, not matching topics)
I would be dubious of (B), (C), and (D) on this question because they seem to be baiting me into thinking the number 1000 is critical to the flaw.
There's actually a common name for the recurring flaw found in the original: Part to Whole.
This flaw occurs when an author assumes that some trait that applies to a certain part therefore applies to the whole.
This flaw also works in reverse, in which case we often call it Whole to Part.
Here are a couple examples:
Each member of this new committee is an efficient worker. Thus, this will be an efficient committee. (part to whole)
It is wrong for an individual to have power over government, so therefore it is wrong for society, a collection of individuals, to have power over government. (part to whole)
Collectively, the pillars on this building are enough to support the weight of the roof. Therefore, each pillar on its own could support the weight of the roof. (whole to part)
The telltale sign of this flaw is that the same trait is discussed in the premise and in the conclusion.
====other answers====
A) is correct. Since any given card will probably not be an ace, the author thinks we can conclude that all cards will probably never be an ace.
C) is not a part to whole flaw. It's a flaw that's more like "because it's unreasonable to believe that A will happen, it's reasonable to believe that A will never happen"
D) This is not really a flawed argument. The first sentence is, in reality, a flawed notion of probability, but if we accepted the first sentence as true, then we would believe the logic of the conclusion.
E) is the flaw of reversed conditional logic (sometimes called nec/suff conflation). They give us
5 yrs. old --> prob 1 meter tall, and then argue that since someone is 1 meter tall, she is probably 5 yrs. old.