debbie.d.park Wrote:But doesn't C (fails to consider that the way most likely to achieve a particular end may not be the only way to achieve that end) still imply that "other types of economies might be able to achieve maximum total utility"?
ohthatpatrick Wrote:While I agree with everything just said, I think it might not clarify why the previous poster was struggling with (D).
(D) is set up as a conditional statement, but an incredibly confusing one.
Normally, 'Must' indicates something required, and required things go on the right.
But the structure here is weird. I think it's actually an ambiguous structure.
I would say
"squares must always be rectangles"
NOT "rectangles must always be squares"
I want to see
square -> rectangle, not the other way around
So it seems like if I say
X must always be Y
I would diagram it as
X --> Y
And yet, if I say
"Taking the LSAT must always be done by law school applicants", I actually get a statement that conveys that "taking the LSAT" is required.
This means that we get
Law school applicant --> take LSAT
So it seems like if I say
X must always accompany Y
I diagram it as
Y --> X
I'm not quite sensing how we can filter between the square/rectangle example and the LSAT/applicant example.
They seem like the same syntax, but they convey different conditional meanings.
At any rate, somehow LSAT wants us to interpret (D) as
"trying to bring about a condition that ensures an end" must always accompany "the most likely way to achieve an end".
giving us
most likely way -> bring about condition that ensures end
And the contrapositive of this fits the argument
~trying to bring about condition that ensures --> ~most likely way
To be honest, I'm searching for a logical/grammatical leg to stand on, because it seems a little arbitrary how we interpret the conditional in (D).
If I say "Presidents of the US must always be 35+"
I get
Pres --> 35+
But if I say, "Surprise endings must always be the way an M. Night movie ends"
I get
M. Night --> Surprise ending
I think there's something about the word "the" that's doing it, that switches the meaning into something definitional for the 2nd idea.
Sorry I don't have a complete answer. If I have a mental breakthrough later, I'll add it (or if anyone else has an opinion, let me know).
ManhattanPrepLSAT1 Wrote:You're definitely down to the best two answer choices. At this point then, you want to find reasons to eliminate one of the two answer choices, rather than look for reasons to support one over the other.
Notice that towards the end of the first sentence, the argument says, "although other types of economies might be able to achieve [maximum total utility]."
That claim can be used to eliminate answer choice (C). The argument never says that it's the only way to bring about the end, just that it's the way most likely to achieve that end, so answer choice (D) is correct.
I hope that helps, let me know if you still have a hard time seeing this one!
BairnOwl Wrote:ohthatpatrick Wrote:While I agree with everything just said, I think it might not clarify why the previous poster was struggling with (D).
(D) is set up as a conditional statement, but an incredibly confusing one.
Normally, 'Must' indicates something required, and required things go on the right.
But the structure here is weird. I think it's actually an ambiguous structure.
I would say
"squares must always be rectangles"
NOT "rectangles must always be squares"
I want to see
square -> rectangle, not the other way around
So it seems like if I say
X must always be Y
I would diagram it as
X --> Y
And yet, if I say
"Taking the LSAT must always be done by law school applicants", I actually get a statement that conveys that "taking the LSAT" is required.
This means that we get
Law school applicant --> take LSAT
So it seems like if I say
X must always accompany Y
I diagram it as
Y --> X
I'm not quite sensing how we can filter between the square/rectangle example and the LSAT/applicant example.
They seem like the same syntax, but they convey different conditional meanings.
At any rate, somehow LSAT wants us to interpret (D) as
"trying to bring about a condition that ensures an end" must always accompany "the most likely way to achieve an end".
giving us
most likely way -> bring about condition that ensures end
And the contrapositive of this fits the argument
~trying to bring about condition that ensures --> ~most likely way
To be honest, I'm searching for a logical/grammatical leg to stand on, because it seems a little arbitrary how we interpret the conditional in (D).
If I say "Presidents of the US must always be 35+"
I get
Pres --> 35+
But if I say, "Surprise endings must always be the way an M. Night movie ends"
I get
M. Night --> Surprise ending
I think there's something about the word "the" that's doing it, that switches the meaning into something definitional for the 2nd idea.
Sorry I don't have a complete answer. If I have a mental breakthrough later, I'll add it (or if anyone else has an opinion, let me know).
The word "must" indicates a necessary condition and goes on the right. The only times it doesn't are when our brains don't interpret it that way. Here is the example you used, along with the literal translation:
X must always accompany Y
X --> Y
The reason you would translate this sentence as Y --> X is because we interpret the statement as actually being "Y must always be accompanied by X."
Here's a real-world example. Imagine you're at an amusement park:
A parent must always accompany a child.
Parent --> accompanies a child
Yet we don't understand this sentence as saying that if we have a parent, they must be accompanying a child. Maybe that parent left their kid at home instead. When we read the sentence, we actually interpret it as saying:
A child must always be accompanied by a parent
Child --> accompanied by parent
As an aside, the words "must" and "must always" are interchangeable for our purposes, with the distinction being that the latter explicitly takes into account the temporal component and the former simply implies it. So I'll just be using "must" from here.
Here's another example:
Cats must eat fish
Cat --> eats fish
Yet if you read the sentence with the emphasis placed on the fish instead of the cat, you could interpret it as saying:
Fish must be eaten by cats
Fish --> eaten by cat
Let's talk about this example you gave: "Surprise endings must always be the way an M. Night movie ends."
The only way it makes sense to interpret this sentence is as follows:
M. Night movies must always be ended by surprise endings
M. Night movie --> ended by surprise ending
This is because we know that surprise endings should not be a subset of M. Night movies; rather, M. Night movies should be a subset of surprise endings. I think this is generally the case with abstract concepts. Consider this example:
Eventually, happiness must find widows.
Widow --> found by happiness
It doesn't make sense to think of happiness as being a subset of widows, because happiness is a broad, universal concept, so interpreting the statement with widows as the sufficient condition works better.
So you should always interpret X must Y as X --> Y unless the Y --> X interpretation is required for the statement to make sense.